National Academies Press: OpenBook

The New Health Care for Profit: Doctors and Hospitals in a Competitive Environment (1983)

Chapter: Ethical Dilemmas of For-Profit Enterprise in Health Care

« Previous: Economic Incentives and Clinical Decisions
Suggested Citation:"Ethical Dilemmas of For-Profit Enterprise in Health Care." Institute of Medicine. 1983. The New Health Care for Profit: Doctors and Hospitals in a Competitive Environment. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/527.
×
Page 125
Suggested Citation:"Ethical Dilemmas of For-Profit Enterprise in Health Care." Institute of Medicine. 1983. The New Health Care for Profit: Doctors and Hospitals in a Competitive Environment. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/527.
×
Page 126
Suggested Citation:"Ethical Dilemmas of For-Profit Enterprise in Health Care." Institute of Medicine. 1983. The New Health Care for Profit: Doctors and Hospitals in a Competitive Environment. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/527.
×
Page 127
Suggested Citation:"Ethical Dilemmas of For-Profit Enterprise in Health Care." Institute of Medicine. 1983. The New Health Care for Profit: Doctors and Hospitals in a Competitive Environment. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/527.
×
Page 128
Suggested Citation:"Ethical Dilemmas of For-Profit Enterprise in Health Care." Institute of Medicine. 1983. The New Health Care for Profit: Doctors and Hospitals in a Competitive Environment. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/527.
×
Page 129
Suggested Citation:"Ethical Dilemmas of For-Profit Enterprise in Health Care." Institute of Medicine. 1983. The New Health Care for Profit: Doctors and Hospitals in a Competitive Environment. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/527.
×
Page 130
Suggested Citation:"Ethical Dilemmas of For-Profit Enterprise in Health Care." Institute of Medicine. 1983. The New Health Care for Profit: Doctors and Hospitals in a Competitive Environment. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/527.
×
Page 131
Suggested Citation:"Ethical Dilemmas of For-Profit Enterprise in Health Care." Institute of Medicine. 1983. The New Health Care for Profit: Doctors and Hospitals in a Competitive Environment. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/527.
×
Page 132
Suggested Citation:"Ethical Dilemmas of For-Profit Enterprise in Health Care." Institute of Medicine. 1983. The New Health Care for Profit: Doctors and Hospitals in a Competitive Environment. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/527.
×
Page 133
Suggested Citation:"Ethical Dilemmas of For-Profit Enterprise in Health Care." Institute of Medicine. 1983. The New Health Care for Profit: Doctors and Hospitals in a Competitive Environment. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/527.
×
Page 134
Suggested Citation:"Ethical Dilemmas of For-Profit Enterprise in Health Care." Institute of Medicine. 1983. The New Health Care for Profit: Doctors and Hospitals in a Competitive Environment. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/527.
×
Page 135
Suggested Citation:"Ethical Dilemmas of For-Profit Enterprise in Health Care." Institute of Medicine. 1983. The New Health Care for Profit: Doctors and Hospitals in a Competitive Environment. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/527.
×
Page 136
Suggested Citation:"Ethical Dilemmas of For-Profit Enterprise in Health Care." Institute of Medicine. 1983. The New Health Care for Profit: Doctors and Hospitals in a Competitive Environment. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/527.
×
Page 137
Suggested Citation:"Ethical Dilemmas of For-Profit Enterprise in Health Care." Institute of Medicine. 1983. The New Health Care for Profit: Doctors and Hospitals in a Competitive Environment. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/527.
×
Page 138
Suggested Citation:"Ethical Dilemmas of For-Profit Enterprise in Health Care." Institute of Medicine. 1983. The New Health Care for Profit: Doctors and Hospitals in a Competitive Environment. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/527.
×
Page 139
Suggested Citation:"Ethical Dilemmas of For-Profit Enterprise in Health Care." Institute of Medicine. 1983. The New Health Care for Profit: Doctors and Hospitals in a Competitive Environment. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/527.
×
Page 140
Suggested Citation:"Ethical Dilemmas of For-Profit Enterprise in Health Care." Institute of Medicine. 1983. The New Health Care for Profit: Doctors and Hospitals in a Competitive Environment. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/527.
×
Page 141
Suggested Citation:"Ethical Dilemmas of For-Profit Enterprise in Health Care." Institute of Medicine. 1983. The New Health Care for Profit: Doctors and Hospitals in a Competitive Environment. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/527.
×
Page 142
Suggested Citation:"Ethical Dilemmas of For-Profit Enterprise in Health Care." Institute of Medicine. 1983. The New Health Care for Profit: Doctors and Hospitals in a Competitive Environment. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/527.
×
Page 143
Suggested Citation:"Ethical Dilemmas of For-Profit Enterprise in Health Care." Institute of Medicine. 1983. The New Health Care for Profit: Doctors and Hospitals in a Competitive Environment. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/527.
×
Page 144
Suggested Citation:"Ethical Dilemmas of For-Profit Enterprise in Health Care." Institute of Medicine. 1983. The New Health Care for Profit: Doctors and Hospitals in a Competitive Environment. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/527.
×
Page 145
Suggested Citation:"Ethical Dilemmas of For-Profit Enterprise in Health Care." Institute of Medicine. 1983. The New Health Care for Profit: Doctors and Hospitals in a Competitive Environment. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/527.
×
Page 146
Suggested Citation:"Ethical Dilemmas of For-Profit Enterprise in Health Care." Institute of Medicine. 1983. The New Health Care for Profit: Doctors and Hospitals in a Competitive Environment. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/527.
×
Page 147
Suggested Citation:"Ethical Dilemmas of For-Profit Enterprise in Health Care." Institute of Medicine. 1983. The New Health Care for Profit: Doctors and Hospitals in a Competitive Environment. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/527.
×
Page 148
Suggested Citation:"Ethical Dilemmas of For-Profit Enterprise in Health Care." Institute of Medicine. 1983. The New Health Care for Profit: Doctors and Hospitals in a Competitive Environment. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/527.
×
Page 149
Suggested Citation:"Ethical Dilemmas of For-Profit Enterprise in Health Care." Institute of Medicine. 1983. The New Health Care for Profit: Doctors and Hospitals in a Competitive Environment. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/527.
×
Page 150
Suggested Citation:"Ethical Dilemmas of For-Profit Enterprise in Health Care." Institute of Medicine. 1983. The New Health Care for Profit: Doctors and Hospitals in a Competitive Environment. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/527.
×
Page 151
Suggested Citation:"Ethical Dilemmas of For-Profit Enterprise in Health Care." Institute of Medicine. 1983. The New Health Care for Profit: Doctors and Hospitals in a Competitive Environment. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/527.
×
Page 152

Below is the uncorrected machine-read text of this chapter, intended to provide our own search engines and external engines with highly rich, chapter-representative searchable text of each book. Because it is UNCORRECTED material, please consider the following text as a useful but insufficient proxy for the authoritative book pages.

Ethical Dilemmas of For-Profit En~re~p~se in Health Care Robert M. Veatch The practice of medicine should not be commercialized nor treated as a commodity of trade. AMA Judicial Council Opinions and Reports, 1969 The type of financial arrangement between a physician and a hospital, corporation or other lay body is important and relevant in determining whether or not such an arrangement is ethical. We further believe that the amount of a physician's income or whether or not an institution is making a profit on his services is irrelevant in whether an arrangement is ethical. AMA Board of Trustees, 1957 The rapid evolution of for-profit corporate delivery of health care over the past few years poses critical questions for those interested in the ethics of health care delivery. The development of commercial dialysis centers, corporate for-profit hospital chains, and other health care delivery systems linking health care to profit-making enterprise raises critical sociological, legal, economic, administrative, and political is- sues. In addition to all of these it challenges some of the most fun- damental ethical presuppositions of both the business and the health · — care communities. The relationship between business and professional health care has always been an ambivalent one. Organized medicine in the United States has never condemned outright the practice of medicine within 125

126 ROBERT M. VEATCH a profit-making context. Yet over the years, beginning with concern about restraining unorthodox practitioners and continuing in debates over physician control of pharmacies, patents, advertising, and finan- cial arrangements in group practice, organized medicine has con- stantly been nervous about the pestilential taint of commercialization. History of the Ethics Controversy The International Context If we are to understand the new ethical problems that may emerge with the evolution of for-profit enterprise in health care, it is worth, first, examining the history of the ethical controversy over some his- torical analogues of that relationship and then attempting to syn- thesize a description of the potential problems to be anticipated. That history reveals that ambiguity has long troubled those trying to un- derstand the relation of medicine to for-profit commercial enterprise. Confucian medicine in ancient China was essentially an art prac- ticed within a family. Each family had someone skilled in medicine who could look after his kin, acting out of the traditional virtues of compassion, applied humaneness, and filial piety. The later profes- sionalization of medicine, so that financial transactions necessarily became a part of the practice of the art, was widely viewed as the beginning of the downfall of the lofty ideals of medicine.) The medical literature of ancient Greece is filled with examples of instances in which it is implied that the motivation of the practitioner might have been something less than applied humaneness. A search of the Hippocratic corpus to find evidence that a philanthropic attitude is essential in medicine proves fruitIess.2 Galen bemoans the fact that philanthropy is the inspiration for only a minority of physicians, be- cause the majority pursue money, honor, or gIory.3 It was standard advice for physicians to choose carefully whom they would accept as patients lest they take on a hopeless case and have their reputations tarnished and their market potential jeopardized by their failure. By the time of the beginnings of modern AngIo-American medical ethics, we still find little attention being paid to the ethics of the business and commercial dimensions of professional health care. One searches the long, detailed Code of Thomas Percival of 1797 in vain for relevant material. This is true even though this code, which was to become the foundation of both British and American medical ethics, was originally written in response to an unsavory feud among phy-

Ethical Dilemmas of For-Profit Enterprise in Health Care 127 sicians, surgeons, and apothecaries at the Manchester Infirmary in England, a fight having the tone of a cutthroat, corporate boardroom machination.4 It was not until the twentieth century that the profes- sional documents of AngIo-American medical ethics began dealing with the specifics of the ethical conundrum of the possibility that medical practice might, to the uninitiated, look something like a busi- ness. A recent British Medical Association document opens its discussion of the topic by stating: "A general ethical principle is that a doctor should not associate himself with commerce in such a way as to let it influence; or appear to influence, his attitude towards the treatment of his patients."5 This is followed by specific prohibitions and approv- als. For example, physicians are to avoid having a financial interest in the sale of pharmaceuticals or writing testimonials. The concern not only focuses on the risk that commercial involvement could affect decisions but also extends to concern about the appearance of being influenced. The Australian Medical Association Code of Ethics has the same principle stated verbatim, with similar examples, followed by an im- possibly convoluted set of sentences attempting to walk a tightrope on the subject of ownership of pharmaceutical companies.6 The American Medical Association The codes of the American Medical Association (AMA) have shown similar ambivalence through the years. To be sure, the positions adopted by the AMA do not always reflect the current views of the American public or even those of American physicians. They surely do not de- scribe actual behavior in all cases. They are, however, the most im- portant consensus statements of organized professional medicine in the United States. As such, they do normally reflect the ideal of what most physicians, at least those who participate in AMA activities, consider to be ethical conduct for physicians. The early codes of the AMA, beginning with the original versions passed at the convention in Philadelphia in IS47, state flat prohibi- tions of certain behavior that everyone seemed to think obviously made the physician too much like a businessman and therefore in danger of ethical misconduct. These codes concentrated on prohibiting advertising, holding of patents, and dispensing "secret nostrums." Act- ing like a businessman was considered unacceptable, but even ap- pearing like one seemed to be as much a cause of concern. During this period medical practitioners whom we now would identify as practic-

128 ROBERT M. VEATCH ing orthodox medicine were very concerned about separating them- seIves from quacks and charlatans, who often engaged in commercial tactics. Advertising The AMA in 1847 stated that: "It is derogatory to the dignity of the profession, to resort to public advertisements or private cards or handbills, inviting the attention of individuals affected with particular diseases...."7 The same declaration is repeated verbatim in the revision of 1903 and in new, even stronger language in the 1912 revision.8 The objection was clearly to the businesslike style of advertising, regardless of content. Publicizing successes, inviting lay- men to witness operations, and boasting of cures were deemed "the ordinary practices of empirics Equacks], and are highly reprehensible in a regular physician." By 1957, with a much shortened set of principles, the prohibition had been reduced to the mandate that the physician "should not solicit patients."9 The interpretation began to get more subtle. Spurred by the Federal Trade Commission's (FTC) suit claiming that prohibition on solicitation was restraining free trade, the AMA began emphasiz- ing that what it wanted to prohibit was "deceptive practices," "false or misleading statements," and the "creation of unjustified expecta- tions." In short, the AMA's position had shifted to one that any good Madison Avenue advertising executive might endorse. What began as an effort to distinguish medical professionals from quacks, and others whom they tried to identify with mere business people, ended up making them demand to be recognized (by the FTC and others) as free-market competitors at their best. Patents A similar progression is seen with the AMA's statements on physician holding of patents. The original position in iS47 was blunt: "It is derogatory to professional character . . . for a physician to hold a patent for any surgical instrument or medicine...."~° By 1971 the practice was acceptable, but nervousness was apparent in the qualifications and warnings. With the major revision in 1981 all signs of ethical doubt about patents had disappeared. It is now stated bluntly that: "It is not unethical for a physician to patent a surgical or diagnostic instrument." Dispensing Pharmaceuticals and Receiving Rebates The older codes explicitly condemn not only the holding of patents but also the pre- scribing of"secret nostrums." Originally the concern was over the secrecy as such, a point that will be important later when we contrast

Ethical Dilemmas of For-ProfIt Enterprise in Health Care 129 professional medical ethics with business ethics.~3 It was more im- portant to distinguish the physician from a charlatan than from a businessman. That same condemnation appeared in the AMA docu- ments into the 1970s when it finally disappeared. Far more important and difficult is the question of whether phy- sicians could sell more orthodox pharmaceuticals. It has long been recognized that physicians who sell their own remedies have a poten- tial conflict of interest. The codes seem to express two concerns: that financial pressures might influence prescribing and that there should be a proper division of labor with pharmacists. From the time of the 1957 revision it was accepted that: "Drugs, remedies or appliances may be dispensed or supplied by the physician provided it is in the best interests of the patient."~4 Because of the potential appearance of conflict of interest and also probably to avoid tensions with phar- macists, the AMA urged physicians "to avoid the regular dispensing and the retail sale of drugs to patients whenever the drug needs of patients can be met adequately by local ethical pharmacies."~5 For similar reasons accepting rebates on prescriptions and appliances has been consistently condemned as unethical. In 1947 the ophthalmologists aggravated the AMA Judicial Council by presenting so many schemes for rebates that the Council was un- characteristically exasperated in its response.~7 Among the tasks of the Council was review of ethical queries from members. Ophthal- mologists were seeking ways in which they could receive some re- muneration, beyond their usual professional fee, for prescribing eye glasses. Rebates from opticians were a common practice. The Council's response was curt: "By far the largest number of requests for infor- mation on approval were received from ophthalmologists who have submitted practically every conceivable plan to circumvent the section of the Principles of Medical Ethics concerning rebates.. .. It is strange that year after year more communications regarding these practices come from members of this particular field than from any other.... No matter how prevalent these practices may have become, they are still unethical." Fee Splitting Closely related to dispensing of pharmaceuticals and receiving rebates is the problem of fee splitting. It has been funda- mental to professional medical ethics since 1912 that fee splitting is unethical, "detrimental to the public good and degrading to the profes- sion," according to the 1912 code. Originally the emphasis was on secrecy in the splitting of fees, but since the 1950s the practice itself, secret or not, has been condemned. It is viewed as an unacceptable

130 ROBERT M. VEATCH inducement that "violates the patient's trust that the physician will not exploit his dependence upon him...." Recently, the economist Mark Pauly has argued forcefully that the absence of fee splitting might also produce undue inducements in this case inducements for the generalist to treat patients who ought to be referred.~9 He concludes that fee splitting ought to be viewed as ethical. While such a conclusion is debatable, at least it suggests that the unanimous, vitriolic condemnation of fee splitting may have latent functions, perhaps, such as maintenance of the idea that the health care professional is significantly different from a business person, for whom commissions, royalties, finder's fees, and the like are standard. Ownership of Health Facilities and Corporate Relations The prob- lems examined thus far advertising, patents, rebates, and fee split- ting constitute the classic issues of the ethics of physician finances. The answers, at least for a time, were simple: Behaving like a rational, self-interested businessman was unethical. Gradually, as the com- plexities of the business of practicing medicine became more clear, qualifications began to cloud the picture. These matters are still rel- atively simple in comparison with the ethical problems of corporate for-profit delivery of health care, in which the ambivalence of the physician/business relation is seen full blown. It is in this context that the ethical tensions of practicing medicine in a for-profit corporate context begin to have their closest analogues with more traditional issues in medical ethics. The first major set of ethical issues is physician ownership of health care facilities. It is now clear that the AMA has concluded that it is acceptable for physicians to own pharmacies20; hospitals2~; nursing homes22; and, by implication, laboratories.23 It also is clear, however, that in all these cases the AMA considers it unethical for a physician to be influenced in his or her medical practice by such ownership. Until the redrafting of the AMA code of ethics in 1980, there was a strict prohibition on any arrangement whereby physicians would profit on investments in proportion to the amount of work they referred to the laboratory.24 Thus, physicians could in fact profit from the refer- rals to pharmacies, nursing homes, hospitals, and laboratories that they owned but were held to a standard in which they acted as if they would not, and in no case could they receive a fee or return on in- vestment directly linked to the business they generated. Still it was considered acceptable for them to share in the profits of the facilities they owned, including the profits they knew they were generating from their own medical practices.

Ethical Dilemmas of For-Profit Enterprise in Health Care 131 The links between the practice of medicine and the corporate com- mercial interest in health care delivery are not always as simple as straightforward ownership by a physician. With physician ownership, professional associations such as the AMA could at least appeal to the recognition that physicians had control of the corporations with which they had financial ties. More complex corporate relations with for- profit enterprise may involve physicians in positions where they ex- ercise much less direct control. The versions of the Judicial Council Opinions ant] Reports of the late 1960s and early 1970s place great emphasis on the ethical prob- lems of physicians practicing within the context of lay-owned corpo- rations or where lay groups profited directly from their service.25 The privilege of healing the sick as ~ profession is a right granted only to those properly qualified and licensed by the state. It is a privilege belonging only to the medical profession. It is a sacrifice of professional dignity that this exclusive right of medicine is so often sold for individual gain or its possessor deprived of it against his will. In increasing numbers, physicians are disposing of their profes- sional attainments to lay organizations under terms which permit a direct profit from the fees or salaries paid for their services to accrue to the lay bodies em- ploying them. Such a procedure is absolutely destructive of that personal re- sponsibility and relationship which is essential to the best interest of the patient.26 The Judicial Council gives three examples. The first is hardly clear- cut: salaries or fees paid to the physician by insurance companies in workman's compensation cases in which the fees allegedly are below the legal fees on which a premium is based. The other two, however, are more directly relevant to for-profit health care enterprise: hos- pitals collecting fees for professional services of staff physicians and absorbing them as hospital income, and universities employing full- time hospital staffs and sharing such fees for the professional care of patients "as to net the university no small profit." Several things are worth noting. First, the cJudicial Council is con- cerned that the right and the dignity of the profession is assaulted by such practices of lay corporations. Second, it believes that such lay involvement destroys professional responsibility and is contrary to the best interest of patients. Finally, underlying much of the Council's concern is a commitment to the maintenance of professional control. The Council's conclusion, one apparently relevant to for-profit health care enterprises, is that: "A physician should not dispose of his profes- sional attainments or services to any hospital, corporation or lay body by whatever name called or however organized under terms or con- ditions which permit the sale of the services of that physician by such an agency for a fee."27

132 ROBERT M. VEATCH The recent evolution of for-profit enterprise in health care has the potential of engaging the physician in a number of capacities: as an employee of a for-profit hospital or other corporation, as an indepen- dent practitioner referring patients to the for-profit corporation for certain medical services, and as an owner of the for-profit corporation. The concern about the dignity of the profession might be a particular problem where physicians are owners. The other forms of participa- tion, however, seem to present even greater difficulty because phy- sicians could lose control over medical practices, abandoning respon- sibility to lay people. By the late 1970s all of this AMA language pertaining to physician relations with lay-owned corporations disappeared, and it was entirely absent from the major revision of the document in 1981. As far as this author has been able to determine, there was no formal change of policy or reversal by any official AMA body. Rather, the warnings against involvement with lay-dominated corporations simply were omitted, leaving the concerned reader to speculate whether the AMA had accommodated the relationship or simply thought it not worth attention any longer. A Summary of the Professional Physician Stance This brief history makes it clear that the attitude of American profes- sional organized medicine toward the commercial aspects of health care has been a complex and ambivalent one. From this complex and shifting pattern of professional attitudes it may be possible to glean a pattern or at least a set of principles that informs the Judicial Council and other AMA pronouncements. Basic Principles of the Professional Stance Service to the Patient Historically, all of medical ethics in the Hip- pocratic tradition, including that of AngIo-American medical ethics, affirms as the basic principle the idea that the physician should use his or her judgment to do what he or she thinks will benefit the patient. it is not surprising, therefore, that the professional stance on the finances of medical practice is normally legitimated by appeal to the welfare of the patient. The condemnation of physicians who allow lay corporations to profit directly from their services is thus characteristic when it ends by arguing that prohibiting such an arrangement is "essential to the best interests of the patient." The AMA's brief in its defense against the FTC's charge that it unlawfully restrained phy- sician advertising was argued in similar terms.

Ethical Dilemmas of For-Profit Enterprise in Health Care 133 Physicians' financial interests are often consistent with many of the practices labeled by the AMA as ethically required. Control of adver- tising and prohibition of lay profits from professional services are obvious examples. This had led some to suggest that self-interested motives have led organized medicine to label certain business prac- tices unethical. In fact the author of an anthropological study of Chinese medical ethics argues that the primary function of medical ethics is the control of financial and other rewards of professional service.28 Pauly's analysis of fee splitting, in contrast to the professional phy- sician literature, simply assumes that physicians will primarily pur- sue self-interest and only at the margin be influenced by patient welfare. Holders of these contrasting attitudes about the role of commitment to patient welfare and self-interest fail to grasp what sociologists some- times refer to as the relationship between the latent and manifest functions of positions adopted and behavior undertaken. There is good reason to believe professionals when they say they are committed to the welfare of their patients. However, this does not necessarily mean that the positions they take about what serves the welfare of their patients may not be influenced by other, more hidden, even subcon- scious agendas and value frameworks unique to their professional group. It also does not exclude the possibility that what they legiti- mately believe will serve patient welfare may also serve other inter- ests as well, including their own. Recently there has been an increasing recognition that the ethics of physician practice is more complex than simply serving the interests of patients. Rights language is increasingly replacing welfare lan- guage. The ethical responsibilities of physicians are increasingly being defined in terms of the rights of patients, instead of in terms of the welfare of patients. The rights language appears formally for the first time in the AMA principles in the revision of 1980. The rights of colleagues and other health care professionals are explicitly affirmed as well as those of patients. It is in the same spirit that the 1981 Opinions of the Judicial Council with regard to patents affirms the "sound doctrine that one is entitled to protect his discovery." Thus, perhaps, part of the softening of the professional opposition to the business imagery is related to the increasing recognition of the legit- imacy of self-interest of health care professionals. Physician Control; of Decision Making anti Fees Within the context of the dominating principle of service to the patient and often legi- timated by it, a second important theme running through the AMA literature is the importance of professional control of decision making and of fees. In no case is the physician's involvement with business

134 ROBERT M. VEATCH condemned when the professional is able to maintain such control. However, paragraphs dealing with professional involvement repeat- edly include the warning that professionals must not lose control of their sphere of responsibility. To the extent that this is a principle underlying the response of professional physician organizations to for-profit health care, it seems clear that physicians will be particularly uncomfortable when the relation is one of the physician as employee of a lay-owned corporation. There may well be less concern when physicians themselves are own- ers of such enterprises. Acceptance of Profit Motive A third basic theme one can deduce from the AMA literature is not stated as boldly but represents an inescapable conclusion. Nowhere in all of the professional literature of AngIo-American medical ethics is there any condemnation of the profit motive in the practice of medicine. While ancient Confucian medicine could look down on those who practiced medicine for finan- cial reward, American medicine is much more open to profit. In fact, as was seen in the second epigraph of this paper, the AMA has viewed the question of whether an institution is making a profit on the phy- sician's services as irrelevant to whether the arrangement is ethical. Suspicion of Commercialization Despite this openness to the profit motive, American professional organized medicine has shown a strong and stubborn resistance to anything it takes to imply the commer- cialization of medical practice. As recently as 1981 the AMA Judicial Council condemned commercialization (while affirming the right to make a "fair compensation"~.29 An Interpretation of the Professional Stance The question of immediate importance for this essay is the relevance of this professional history and the principles derived from it for the evolution of for-profit enterprise in health care delivery. While some of the elements have clear connections with the recent development of commercial hemodialysis and hospital chains owned by large profit- making corporations, there is a sense of discontinuity that some- thing of moral significance is at stake beyond the ethical problems faced by the small-town general practitioner whose income was tied to his or her medical advice. Two major elements seem to be important in the recent developments: commercial motivation of for-profit en- terprise and the subordination of medicine to the objectives of lay people. As we have seen, neither of these by itself is a new concern

Ethical Dilemmas of For-Profit Enterprise in Health Care 135

136 ROBERT M. VEATCH cision-making authority over areas related to patient care and medical practice. Corporate medicine as practiced by company physicians is the clos- est analogue and that is a small-scale development in comparison with the potential of for-profit enterprise. Traditional organized med- icine, if this is correct, was capable of tentative accommodation to the complex realities of the business of medicine when some commer- cialization was involved, provided physicians retained dominance in medical decision making. It was also willing to accommodate the real- ities of lay control (i.e., trustees, administrators, and the sponsoring organization's mission), provided the objectives were civic or chari- table. The two elements coming together, however, may well pose new challenges that will test to its utmost the ability of the profession to accommodate. This may partially explain why the for-profit hospital typically increases physician membership on hospital boards. Physicians Compared with Other Professionals The problems faced by physicians who practice medicine in the setting of a for-profit enterprise are likely to be similar to those faced by other professionals. A full examination of the histories of the ethics of other professional groups has not been possible, but the results of a limited exploration have not been encouraging. The professional groups of accountants, engineers, lawyers, and public policy analysts have been examined to determine if their longer history of dealings with large profit-making corporations could shed light on potential moral ten- sions between the professional and his or her employers. It became apparent quickly that serious disanalogies among the professions limit the usefulness of the comparison. Certified public accountants (CPAs), for example, have in their dominant code (the "Rules of Conduct" of the American Institute of Certified Public Accountants) strong state- ments requiring the independence of accountants.3i No financial ties of any kind are permitted with the enterprise for whom the accountant is expressing an opinion on financial statements. There is no direct condemnation of a CPA serving as an employee of a corporation, but such a relationship clearly would be counterproductive to certain func- tions of CPAs. The primary purpose of the CPA is to assure outsiders of the reliability of financial statements of a corporation. Financial independence is essential for the certification to be trustworthy. It is thus in the nature of the role relation that the accountant be inde- pendent. No similar role requirements force a physician to be inde- pendent of an enterprise providing health care.

Ethical Dilemmas of For-Profit Enterprise in Health Care 137 Engineers, by contrast, have long since accommodated to perform- ing their work as employees of for-profit corporations. Several differ- ent societies of engineers serve as professional organizations for various speciality branches of engineering. Several have no formal codes at all. Six groups (including those for chemical, industrial, agricultural, civil, mechanical, and ceramic engineers) subscribe to the "Canons of Ethics of Engineers" of the Engineers' Council for Professional De- velopment, the umbrella organization of the professional societies of engineers. None of their codes, including the "Canons" of the Engi- neers' Council, raises any question about an engineer working as an employee of a corporation. In fact, an employer-employee relationship is assumed. The sections dealing with the engineer's relation with the public and with employers provide the closest analogies that have been located to the kinds of problems a physician might face if em- ployed by a for-profit corporation owning a hospital or other health care facility. These sections make clear that the engineer has a direct obligation to the public to have a proper regard for safety, health, and welfare; to extend public knowledge; and to "indicate to his employer or client the adverse consequences to be expected if his engineering judgment is overruled."32 The essence of the engineering position is clear; employment in a for-profit corporation may pose ethical prob- lems calling forth the ethical integrity of the engineer, but with dil- igence any such problems can be overcome. Since some engineers own their own engineering corporations, we might hope to find here some guidance on cases where physicians might become owners of for-prof~t health care facilities. Such a hope would be frustrated, however. Other than these vague comments on the engineer's obligation to the public, there are no comments on potential conflict between the engineer-owner's commercial self- interest and the interest of the client. Lawyers represent an intermediate case. There is some literature on the practice of law in a corporate setting.33 It reveals that lawyers have a long history of employment within the corporate nexus, yet emphasizes their independence. The older version of the Canons of Professional Ethics of the American Bar Association includes a rel- evant provision originally adopted in 1928. This provision states that "the professional services of a lawyer should not be controlled or ex- ploited by any lay agency, personal or corporate, which intervenes between the client and the lawyer."34 The same provision makes clear that it is acceptable for a lawyer to be employed by an organization but then goes on to place a critical limitation prohibiting legal services to persons within the organization. An important feature of providing

138 ROBERT M. VEATCH health care by corporate for-profit enterprises is that the recipient of the professional's services is an individual—not the corporation itself. In fact the corporation may have a financial interest in seeing that the individual client gets something other than the best medical ser- vices. By contrast most professionals engineers, accountants, and corporate lawyers are providing their professional services directly for the benefit of the corporation. If they have a responsibility to outsiders, it is to some vague "public," not generally to individual consumers of their services. Lawyers, like physicians, might theoretically provide their services to individuals, say members of an organization, while on the payroll of that organization. It is this that the AMA Canons of Professional Ethics (in elect until 1976) expressly prohibits.35 Thus, examples of situations directly analogous to the problems of providing health care in a corporate setting did not arise in the lawyer's context, at least until recently. A search of early ethical opinions from the Committee on Ethics and Professional Responsibility of the AMA failed to reveal any cases of relevance.36 It appears that many of the more critical problems anticipated in the health care sphere either do not arise in accounting, engineering, and law or are not considered insurmountable. Problems of constrain- ing services deemed by the professional to be necessary but rejected by the corporation as inefficient do not get addressed, for example. Neither do problems of excluding clients who cannot pay market prices for the professionals services. In none of the other professions do the problems of professionals functioning as owners of a profit-making enterprise get attention, either because they do not play that role or because the problems arising when they do play it are apparently not considered serious. It appears that little will be gained by examining further the codes of other professional groups. Their situations are too different. They have not addressed adequately the problems when they are analogous, and the services at stake are arguably morally differ- ent. Even if engineering or accounting services are justifiably dis- tributed by the use of market mechanisms, it is not clear that health care services would be. A Philosophical Evaluation of the Problem Problems with Evaluations Based on Professional Codes The commission for this paper emphasized examination of the ways in which physician involvement in for-prof~t health care enterprise has been addressed in professional codes of ethics. We have seen that

Ethical Dilemmas of For-Profit Enterprise in Health Care 139 there is a great deal of concern, much marginally relevant material from an earlier era, and a great deal of residual ambivalence of the professional codes to any long-term resolution of the problems of con- cern to the Institute of Medicine. In the first place, it is clear that the codes have shifted considerably over the years from an explicit antipathy to the business connotations of such matters as advertising to the adoption of a position that seems little different from that of any ethically practiced business concern. More critically, it is not clear how the particular positions of profes- sional groups should be taken into account by the broader public in formulating policy, even when those positions are stated unambigu- ously. At most, the positions expressed in professional codes reflect the moral consensus of the profession. More realistically they reflect the consensus of the segment of the profession that actively participates in organized professional matters. It is well known that such activists do not necessarily reflect the full range of the members of the profes- sion. Even if they did, however, there is a broader philosophical prob- lem in relying on the codes articulated by professional groups for determining the proper norms for ethical relationships between professionals and the broader public. In spite of the arguments that abound about the latent, more self- serving functions of professional codes, this author is convinced that it is reasonable to take these codes as good-faith expressions of what professions consider to be ethical conduct for members of their groups. The fact that the codes reflect a good-faith consensus of what the professional groups take to be ethical conduct is not enough to legit- imate the use of the codes for resolving matters of professional ethics. For a rule of ethical conduct to be justified it must conform to a set of basic ethical principles derived from sources that are far more uni- versal and far more fundamental than mere professional consensus. Exactly what those sources are remains a matter of dispute. The great religious traditions see the basic principles as coming from God, per- haps reflected in moral natural laws. Our founding fathers saw them as self-evident truths. Some philosophers see them as derived from a basic social contract. In any case these basic principles are something shared by an entire moral community; they are not the exclusive property of a group, professional or otherwise, within the community. Thus, it is always possible to ask of a statement appearing in a profes- sional code: Even though the professional group agrees that a given behavior is ethically appropriate, it is really consistent with the basic principles of our ethical system? The code itself can never be taken by a society as the ultimate test of the morality of a lay-professional

140 ROBERT M. VEATCH relationship. A full ethical analysis of the role of physicians in for- profit health care enterprise must include an examination of the basic ethical issues, not merely an effort to determine what the professional code writers believe to be ethical. Basic Philosophical Themes Business Ethics and Physician Ethics: The Role of Altruism The most fundamental ethical issue arising when the physician confronts the world of business is whether the ethic of the physician is com- patible with that of the business world. It has been argued that the ethical obligations that define the role of the physician are derived from basic ethical principles shared by the moral community of lay persons and professionals. Thus, in principle the ethics of business and the ethics of a profession should have a common foundation. Dif- ferent individual roles in a society, however, may require radically different moral actions even though the moral obligations defining those roles are all derived from a common set of principles. Parents, teachers, and police officers ought to treat adolescents differently even though they all subscribe to the same system of ethical principles. Likewise, it may be that business people and physicians ought to act somewhat differently toward clients even though they subscribe to the same general principles. A commonly held stereotype that expresses such differences is that physicians and other health care professionals are expected to act primarily or exclusively for the welfare of the patient, whereas it is perfectly acceptable for an ordinary business person to pursue self- interest even at the expense of the welfare of others. In the literature on the sociology of the professions, professionals are distinguished from occupations by what Talcott Parsons called "collectivity orien- tation."37 That is, they pursue interests common to the group rather than just self-interest. It is what in ethics would be referred to as altruism rather than egoism. By contrast business persons are self- oriented or egoistic; they are not expected to put the welfare of others above or even on the same plane as their own interests. It is not that business people are being selfish and immoral. Rather, it is considered ethically appropriate for the business person to pursue self-interest when in the business role. As long as that fundamental ethical dis- tinction holds, it is apparent that it will be extremely difficult for the health care professionals role to be embedded a business context. When professionals are employees of profit-making corporations, pur- suing their role predictably would clash with business persons within

Ethical Dilemmas of For-Profit Enterprise in Health Care 141 the corporation pursuing theirs. When professionals are themselves owners of for-profit health care enterprises, they would themselves experience the conflict of trying to fill the two roles simultaneously. There is good evidence, however, that the distinction between self- and collectivity orientation is overstated and much too simplistic. It has already been pointed out that health care professionals themselves are increasingly recognizing the legitimacy of a muted self-interest in their ethics. On the other hand, it is clear that the ethic of business has never been one in which anything goes as long as self-interest is served. It is safe to say that virtually no business person believes that business people should lie, cheat, steal, or harm others. (Of course, in the world of business, just as in the world of professions, no one always conforms perfectly to the norm of what should be done.) Business people see themselves as having many characteristics in common with professionals, including the recognition of moral limits on pursuit of self-interest. Physicians, on the other hand, increasingly see them- seIves as having elements in common with business persons, including a degree of legitimate self-interest. This is not to say that the ethical norms for physicians and for business people are identical. It is clear they are not. The difference cannot be reduced simplistically, however, to a difference between self- and collectivity orientations. What is as stake may be the extent to which society expects people in each role to be altruistic. It may be that certain limited acts of kindness and other-regarding actions are expected of the business community. Business people widely follow the practice of making char- itable contributions and engaging in other beneficent actions, not all of which can be attributed to enlightened self-interest. These, espe- cially if they involve substantial contribution, are typically viewed as supererogatory, as acts above and beyond what strict morality re- qu~res. On the other hand, although the codes of physicians contain plat- itudes about the welfare of the patient always taking absolute moral precedence, physicians recognize that there are legitimate moral lim- its on the obligation to sacrifice self-interest for the welfare of others. Virtually no study has been made within the ethics of professions to examine the real moral limits on the professional's duty to be collec- tivity oriented or on the relation between the professional's obligation to be altruistic in comparison with the business person's. Deontologiccll versus Consequentialist Ethics Another potential but unexplored difference between professional and business ethics may

142 ROBERT M. VEATCH be found in the technical distinction made by philosophical ethicists between deontological and consequentiaTist modes of reasoning. It is now well established that physicians, in their traditional professional ethics, are uniquely consequentiaTist in their moral reasoning. They evaluate actions strictly on the basis of the consequences they produce. Physician ethics is even more unique in that in comparison to, say, public policy analysts, many of whom also are consequentialist in their ethics, the relevant consequences for physicians are limited, at least in the classical expressions of the Hippocratic tradition, to those ac- cruing to patients (rather than to other individuals, bystanders, or society at large). Thus, this consequentialist thinking differs from classical utilitarianism. To this author's knowledge, no thorough study of the normative ethical structure of the business community has ever been under- taken. ~ would predict, however, that although the business ethic is not immune from consequentialist thinking, especially of the utili- tarian type, it is much closer to the traditional religious ethics (es- pecially Jewish and Protestant ethics) and the secular liberal tradition of our political and cultural heritage (stemming from natural law theory, Locke, Hobbes, Kant, and the American founding fathers). As different as these traditions are, they all share a common feature: They all maintain that there is more to ethics than simply producing good consequences. hying, breaking promises, violating the liberty of others, and killing are characteristics of actions that tend to make them wrong even if in a particular instance bad consequences do not flow from those actions. This position is what ethicists call deonto- logical ethics. A brief examination of the codes of the business com- munity reveals tendencies to display that kind of reasoning in addition to utilitarian patterns. Business people think it is wrong to lie, cheat, and steal, and they do not have to determine the consequences before they reach that conclusion. If so, they are very different from physi- cians in their traditional consequentialist ethical theory. Health Care as a Commodity One possibility is that the difference between business and professional ethics is not in the roles of the participants but in the nature of the "product." It is currently being debated heatedly whether health care is unique among the goods and services in which people potentially have an interest. On the one hand, some argue that health care is like any other commodity like beer or panty hose, to use the language of one who takes this position. It should be sold in the market to those who have the capacity to buy. After all, it is pointed out, such other basic necessities as food, clothing,

Ethical Dilemmas of For-Profit Enterprise in Health Care 143 and shelter are sold similarly. This is the position of the libertarians, under the influence of entitlement theorists,38 and of health care the- orists under that sphere of influence.39 From such a philosophical perspective, it is easy to see how health care could become part of for- profit corporate enterprise without any moral tensions. On the other hand, some see health care as more fundamental. While it is recognized that people cannot have an unlimited right to all the health care they could possibly want, health care is viewed as different from other goods and services, something to which one has some kind of moral right. It is viewed that way because it is funda- mental to survival, because the need for it is distributed so unevenly, or because it is necessary to enjoy the basic social goods of life.40 It is a position rooted in more patterned theories of distributive justice.4i The implications are radical if one views health care as some sort of right and thus different from mere business commodities. It makes the delivery of health care in a business setting almost impossible. The implications extend far beyond corporate for-profit enterprises of the kind that are beginning to emerge on the American scene. All distribution of health care on an economic basis is called into question, even the more traditional professional private-practitioner/fee-for-ser- vice arrangements. The profit motive itself, which we have seen to be compatible with traditional professional physician ethics, is jeopar- dized in the health care sphere if health care is a right. The Double Agent Problem Another basic theme that makes the business/health care relationship unique is what has been referred to by medical ethicists over the past decade as the double agent problem. As we have seen, many business/professional relationships involve relatively simple diadic interactions in which the professional is en- gaged by the corporation to serve the corporation's interest. The law- yer or engineer performs the services needed by the corporation. In relatively rare circumstances the professional is hired by the orga- nization to provide professional services directly for a client who may have interests quite different from the organization's. The professional is simultaneously an agent for the organization and an individual client. The term double agent problem was first used to describe the position of a psychiatrist employed by a medical school to provide psychiatric services to medical students but who was also to advise the school on the suitability of students for continuation or reentry into its educational program.42 A physician employed by a corporation who would sell his or her services to customers of the corporation is potentially in the classical

144 ROBERT M. VEATCH double agent bind. Loyalty to the corporation may conflict with that which is traditionally owed to the patient. It is not yet clear what the proper ethical dynamic should be for a professional in a double agent situation. Some argue that professionals simply cannot function in such a situation. That would mean that no physician should be work- ing for a profit-making corporation if the agenda were potentially in conflict with that of patients (which it always would be). Most now consider that answer too simple. In at least some carefully guarded contexts health care professionals are thought to be acting ethically while having divided loyalties. Company physicians offering employment physical exams, for example, are widely accepted. The strategy that is evolving is one of developing principles for reducing or eliminating conflict of interest. For example, principles of disclosure are being formulated. All parties should know in advance exactly what kinds of information should be disclosed to employers and what to keep confidential. If physicians in a corporate setting are expected to make cost containment decisions whereby patients might not receive all the care that was potentially beneficial to them, at the very least the physician would be expected to disclose to all parties that such decisions were part of his or her role. It is unlikely, however, that full disclosure alone will solve the double agent problem. As the practice of medicine in a for-profit enterprise evolves, a study of additional safeguards and guidelines to minimize conflict of interest must be developed. Differences Between Business and Physician Ethics It has been argued that it is too simple to distinguish between the ethics of the physician and the business person by holding that phy- sicians, as professionals, are collectively oriented and business people are self-oriented. Still it was held that there are differences in tra- ditional ethical expectations in the two roles. In this section several of the more specific examples ofthese conflicts will be presented, based on a review of the literature of business and professional ethics and general knowledge of traditional patterns and beliefs. It is suggested that these more specific ethical problems will likely constitute the heart of the ethical tension between business and professional models if and when the practice of medicine in a for-profit setting becomes dominant. Lying and Deception Before turning to several examples of direct relevance to health care economics, it is interesting to note one ex-

Ethical Dilemmas of For-Profiit Enterprise in Health Care 145 ample of ethical differences between health care professionals and business people that supports the claim that the ethical differences are more complex than the common stereotype would admit. It is fair to say that there is nothing in business ethics that requires telling the "whole truth" about one's product. Certain disclosures are surely required, but the weak points or inadequacies of one's product need not be emphasized. Still an outright lie misrepresenting one's product, claiming that it has some property that it does not have, is ethically unacceptable in the business community. (Again, this is not to say it does not happen, but when it does no one in the business community is going to defend the lie as morally acceptable). By contrast, in professional physician ethics the dominant moral principle has been the welfare of the patient. Deception, misinfor- mation, and outright lies have been defended morally when done in the name of protecting patient welfare to avoid traumatizing a ter- minal cancer patient or to entice a patient into needed medical treat- ment. The professional ethical evaluation of this practice has changed rapidly over the past decade.43 Such deception is now widely rejected among physicians. The newest version of the Principles of Medical Ethics of the AMA holds the physician to "deal honestly with pa- tients." That is a new recognition of the rights of patients. Prior to these recent developments, however, physicians and business people had clear differences on the morality of lying differences, oddly enough, in which the business person held a position closer to traditional West- ern morality. Competitor's Use of Outdated Information The remaining di~er- ences that will be identified between physician morality and business morality relate directly to tensions one can anticipate in the evolution of the practice of medicine in for-profit corporate settings. Consider, as a first example, a situation in which a practitioner discovers that a competitor is making business decisions based on outdated, erro- neous, or inadequate information. If that individual is in the business world, this is likely to be a cause for rejoicing. Nothing in the ethics of business would call for that business person to point this fact out to his competitor. In fact, he or she would be expected to take advan- tage of it to improve the market position of the business. A physician discovering that a colleague is using outdated, erro- neous, or inadequate information is morally in a very different posi- tion. Such a physician bears an obligation to take reasonable steps to enlighten the colleague, transmit up-to-date information, and if nec- essary even take action to make sure that the colleague practices

146 ROBERT M. VEATClI competently. The difference in the relation is signaled by the shift in language from competitor to colleague. A physician who works for one profit-making corporation and who learns that a colleague who works for a competing hospital is using an outmoded practice that will even- tually be disadvantageous to his or her employer as well as the pa- tients would find it difficult at best to fulfill simultaneously the traditional ethical expectations of both business and professional med- clne. Enticement of Customers into Needless Consumption Another area of potential tension is in practices that entice customers to consume. It is widely accepted in business through advertising, packaging, and other promotion techniques that it is not only ethical but also nec- essary business strategy to create a market for one's product. A good profit-oriented hospital should be expected to do just that by pro- moting elective procedures; making efficient use of resources; and encouraging or giving incentives to physicians to "order" marginal tests, treatments, and services. Although business people probably would find unacceptable the intentional inducement of a consumer to use a product that would actually be harmful, little objection is ever offered to harmless enticement to consume. In medicine the traditional pattern is quite different. Although phy- sicians may engage in practices that serve only to generate extra business for them, such practices are certainly considered unethical. In the extreme, such as in Medicaid "mills," universal condemnation is the response. Once one realizes that many procedures, tests, and treatments are quite marginal—that a patient will neither be helped nor hurt greatly by an intervention—the problem becomes more crit- ical. Physicians can expect to come under great pressure from cor- porate managers to generate work in these areas. Exclusion of Inefficient Customers Another common, prudent busi- ness practice is the exclusion of customers who can only be serviced inefficiently. If a company services a large market, one portion of which is sparsely populated and is being serviced at a loss, a corporate executive would be viewed as foolish perhaps even unethical in squandering stockholders' resources- were he or she to fad] to close the territory that placed a drain on the company. In medicine efforts to exclude service to areas and individuals who can be served only at relatively great cost are much more suspect. The closing of a rural clinic or a government decision to transfer public health service personnel away from sparsely settled areas would cer-

Ethical Dilemmas of For-Profit Enterprise in Health Care 147 tainly meet with controversy. For-profit health care corporations pro- viding hospital care are certain to face conflict over these divergent patterns of expectation. The morally correct solution to this dilemma probably will depend directly on whether health care is a right or a mere commodity. The Duty to the Indigent Another dilemma closely related to the question of whether health care is a right is what business people and physicians feel they owe to those who cannot afford to purchase ser- vices at the prevailing market rate. No business person would think that he or she has a duty to provide a Mercedes or even a Ford to those who cannot adore to buy one, but physicians traditionally have held some sense of responsibility to those too poor to buy medical care. Physicians have acknowledged both charity work and the principle of the sliding-scale fee. Although sometimes these are acknowledged more in theory than in practice (one study in Connecticut revealed that no analytical psychiatrist treated patients for free, though there were limited cases of fee reduction),44 some sense of responsibility, collective or individual, is still acknowledged. Hospitals receiving Hill- Burton funds are obligated by law to offer services to the indigent. It is predictable that physicians will fee] tension with their corporate employers when indigent patients arrive at the hospital door needing unavoidable medical services. Supplying Unprofitable Products ancl Services One of the great problems faced by the business mode', especially if health care is considered a right of more rigorous claim than mere commodities, is how goods and services that lack profit potential will ever be produced. We already face that problem with the production of drugs and bio- logicals for rare conditions in which commercial production can never be profitable. Similar problems exist potentially for goods and services in hospitals and other commercially owned health care facilities. The development of surgeons trained to perform rarely needed surgical procedures could probably never take place in a purely market model. Certain types of medical interventions are more easily provided for a fee than others. Some concern has already been expressed that drug, surgical, and other treatment interventions will be overemphasized at the expense of dietary and lifestyle changes because it is difficult to collect as lucrative a fee for counseling as for more tangible services. Any intervention strategy that however elective lacks profit potential may be jeopardized in the for-profit enterprise system of health care delivery.

148 ROBERT M. VEATCH Of course, these problems have been faced already. Some drug com- panies conduct important work on pharmaceuticals that they know lack profit potential. They do so for the public relations value but probably also out of a limited sense of altruism. Moreover, the gov- ernment carries a substantial portion of the burden for research and development in areas for which the profit incentive is inadequate. If for-profit health care enterprise becomes more widespread, it may have to be supplemented by a governmental support network for re- search, development, and delivery of products and services lacking profit potential. Differing Concepts of Self-Reguic~tion One of the chief character- istics of a profession well recognized by the sociology of the professions is that professionals, as opposed to those merely engaged in business, have substantial authority for self-regulation. This is expressed in a professional role in licensure, certification, supervision of curriculum, disciplinary proceedings, and accreditation. By contrast, the business world basically has been exempt from efforts of self-regulation. Vol- untary efforts have been weak, reliant on moral suasion, and widely regarded as ineffective. There are both theoretical and practical reasons professional self- regulation in these areas has come under severe criticism. In theory, if professional groups have unique ethical and other value commit- ments, then even perfect self-regulation will sometimes produce re- sults that are unacceptable to the broader community. On the practical level it is widely recognized that the pressures of conflict of interest and comradeship make elective self-regulation extremely difficult. Thus, there is strong pressure for society to treat the professions more like businesses, with a combination of internal voluntary efforts, reg- ulatory restraint, judicial control, and public accountability. Still we can anticipate potential tension, for example, when physicians in a commercially owned hospital feel accountable to outsiders within their profession and the business managers resist professional efforts to control their business practices. Conclusion We can anticipate many points of ethical difficulty as for-profit health care enterprises evolve and force more direct interactions between the medical profession and its system of ethics and business with its sys- tem of ethics. It is not yet clear what the organized professional phy- sician response will be to these developments. We can anticipate that

Ethical Dilemmas of For-Profit Enterprise in Health Care 149 physicians will be concerned with any removal of professional control from medical decision making and will be uncomfortable with the assault on their dignity that would accompany an increase in the image of commercialization of the physician's role. Still we have re- peatedly seen the organized profession accommodate change by mov- ing in the direction of the business model. Shifts on advertising, accommodation to ownership of health facilities, repeated endorse- ments of the legitimacy of the profit motive, and adjustments to tol- erate the employment of the professional within lay organizations all point to the flexibility of the profession on such matters and its ability to accommodate the realities of health care as an industry. It is not clear what the public ought to say regarding the practice of medicine in a for-profit commercial setting. An initial intuitive resistance to it is grounded in the traditional high regard for the medical professional, an unwillingness to view the physician as part of a business operation, and a feeling that health care should be sup- plied (within some reasonable limits) on the basis of need rather than ability to pay. If the debate over whether all of health care should be insulated from the market of supply and demand leads to the conclu- sion that it should be, then public resistance to medicine within a for- profit enterprise would be expected. On the other hand, the case can be made for a further opening toward the practice of medicine in this way. Many of the recent changes in professional physician ethics the development of the rights perspec- tive, the movement away from an exclusively consequentialist ethic, and the acceptance of the legitimacy of a limited self-interest stem from lay pressures on the professional community to return to the mainstream of Western ethics. Physicians and lay people alike may find attractive a liberation from the unreasonable expectation of un- limited altruism on the part of physicians. Such an adjustment would make the lay-professional relationship a more realistic one of equal human beings, each of whom has something to gain from an inter- action. Moreover, if our society is moving away from professional self- regulation and toward more public mechanisms of control comparable to those now in place in the business community, the evolution of a for-profit commercial medical system might facilitate that shift. The time has come to explore in much greater depth the ethical tensions that will arise as for-profit health care systems controlled by nonprofessional business interests begin to gain a greater position in our society. Study is needed both of the more theoretical differences between professional and business ethics and the specific ethical prob- lems that are likely to arise.

150 References and Notes ROBERT M. VEATCH 1. The early seventeenth-century figure, Kunh T'ing-hsein, complained ofthe physicians who were his contemporaries: "When they visit the rich, they are conscientious; when they deal with the poor, they act carelessly. This is the eternal peculiarity of those who practice medicine as a profession, and not as applied humaneness." Cited in Paul U. Unschuld, Medical Ethics in Imperial China (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1979), p. 74. 2. Darrel W. Amundsen, "The Physician's Obligation to Prolong Life: A Medical Duty Without Classical Roots," Hastings Center Report 8 (August 1978), pp. 23-30. 3. Galen, De Placitis 9, 5, as cited in Darrel W. Amundsen, op. cit., p. 24. 4. Thomas Percival, Percival's Medical Ethics, edited by Chauncey D. Leake (Baltimore: Williams & Wilkins, 1927). 5. British Medical Association, Medical Ethics (London: British Medical Association House, 1974). 6. The Australian Code informed the physician that: "A doctor should not have a fi- nancial interest in the sale of any pharmaceutical preparation that he may recommend to a patient...." But at the same time, "this is not held to apply to the acquisition of shares in a public company marketing pharmaceutical products, subject to the provision that the acquisition of shares is not conditional on ordering products of the company...." Australian Medical Association, Code of Ethics (Glebe, Sidney: Australian Medical Association, 1975 edition), p. 24. 7. American Medical Association, Code of Medical Ethics, adopted by the AMA in Phil- adelphia, May 1847, and by the New York Academy of Medicine in October 1847 (New York: H. Ludwig & Co., 1848), p. 17. 8. "Principles of Medical Ethics of the American Medical Association," 1903, 1912. Reprinted in Percival's Medical Ethics, op. cit. pp. 244, 260. 9. American Medical Association, Judicial Council and Reports (Chicago: American Medical Association, 1971), p. 23. 10. American Medical Association, Code of Medical Ethics, adopted by the AMA at Phil- adelphia, May 1847, and by the New York Academy of Medicine in October 1847 (New York: H. Ludwig, & Co., 1848), p. 17. 11. "It is not unethical for-a physician to patent a surgical or diagnostic instrument . . . but in the interest of the public welfare and the dignity of the profession [medicine] insists that once a patent is obtained by a physician . . . the physician may not ethically use his patent right to retard or inhibit research or to restrict the benefit derivable from the patented article. Any physician who obtains a patent and uses it for his own aggrandizement or financial interest to the detriment of the profession or the public is acting unethically." Judicial Council Opinions and Reports (Chicago: American Medical Association, 1971), p. 13. 12. In fact it is gratuitously added that: "The laws governing patents are based on the sound doctrine that one is entitled to protect his discovery." Current Opinions of the Judicial Council of the American Medical Association (Chicago: American Medical Association, 1981), p. 29. 13. "If such nostrum be of real efficacy," says the 184? code, "any concealment regarding it is inconsistent with beneficence and professional liberality; and, if mystery alone give it value and importance, such craft implies either disgraceful ignorance, or fraudulent ava- rice." Code of Medical Ethics, adopted by the American Medical Association at Philadelphia, May 1847, and by the New York Academy of Medicine in October 1847 (New York: H. Ludwig & Co., 1848), p. 17. 14. American Medical Association, Judicial Council Opinions and Reports (Chicago: American Medical Association, 1971), pp. 37, 48. 15. Ibid., p. 48. 16. Ibid., p. 41; Current Opinions of the Judicial Council of the American Medical As- sociation (Chicago: American Medical Association, 1981), p. 20.

Ethical Dilemmas of Por-Profit Enterprise in Health Care 151 17. "Report of the Judicial Council of the American Medical Association." Journal of the American Medical Association 134 (May 10, 1947), p. 178. 18. Judicial Council Opinions and Reports (Chicago: American Medical Association, 1971), p. 37. 19. Mark V. Pauly, "The Ethics and Economics of Kickbacks and Fee Splitting," Bell Journal of Economics 10 (September 1979), pp. 334-352. 20. Current Opinions of the Judicial Council of the American Medical Association (Chi- cago: American Medical Association, 1971), p. 24. 21. Ibid., p. 11. 22. Ibid. 23. Ibid., pp. 25-26. 24. Judicial Council Opinions and Reports (Chicago: American Medical Association, 1977), p. 39. 25. Jud icial Council Opinion and Reports (Chicago: American Medical Association, 1969), pp. 32-35; Judicial Council Opinions and Reports (Chicago: American Medical Association, 1971), pp. 31-33. 26. Judicial Council Opinion and Reports (Chicago: American Medical Association, 1969), p. 32. 27. Ibid., pp. 32-33. 28. Paul U. Unschuld, Medical Ethics in Imperial China (Berkeley: University of Cali- fornia Press, 1979). 29. Speaking of the physician's relation with laboratories, it said: "As a professional man, the physician is entitled to fair compensation for his services. He is not engaged in a commercial enterprise and he should not make a markup, commission, or profit on the services rendered by others." Current Opinions of the Judicial Council of the American Medical Association (Chicago: American Medical Association, 1981), p. 26. 30. Robert M. Veatch, Case Studies in Medical Ethics (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1977), pp. 61-64. 31. Jane Clapp, Professional Ethics and Insignia (Metuchen, N.J.: Scarecrow Press, Inc., 1974), p 9 32. Ibid., pp. 247-248. 33. Clarence Walton, The Ethics of Corporate Conduct (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice- Hall, 1977), pp. 305-338. 34. "The professional services of a lawyer should not be controlled or exploited by any lay agency, personal or corporate, which intervenes between the client and lawyer." Henry S. Drinker, Legal Ethics (Westport, Conn.: Greenwood Press, 1980), p. 322. 35. Ibid. Employment in an organization, such as an association, club, or trade organi- zation, was acceptable provided the lawyer rendered legal services to that organization, "but this employment should not include the rendering of legal services to the members of such an organization in respect to their individual affairs." 36. Recent Ethics Opinions: Committee on Ethics and Professional Responsibility (Chi- cago: American Bar Association, from March 1969 to July 1976). 37. Talcott Parsons, The Social System (New York: The Free Press, 1951), p. 434. 38. Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State and Utopia (New York: Basic Books, 1974). 39. H. Tristram Engelhardt, Jr., "Health Care Allocations: Response to the Unjust, the Unfortunate, and the Undesirable," In Earl Shelp, ed. Justice and Health Care (Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel Publishing Co., 1981), pp. 121-137. 40. Ronald Green, "Health Care and Justice in Contract Theory Perspective," Robert M. Veatch and Roy Branson, eds. Ethics and Health Policy (Cambridge: Ballinger, 1976), pp. 111-126.; Gene Outka, "Social Justice and Equal Access to Health Care," Journal of Re- ligious Ethics 2 (Spring 1974), pp. 11-32; Robert M. Veatch, A Theory of Medical Ethics (New York: Basic Books, 1981), pp. 250-287.

152 ROBERT M. VEATCH 41. John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1971); Chris- topher Abe, "Justice as Equality," Philosophy and Public Affairs 5 (Fall 1975), pp. 69-89. 42. Willard Gaylin and Daniel Callahan, "The Psychiatrist as Double Agent," Hastings Center Report 4 (February 1974), pp. 12-14. 43. Robert M. Veatch and Ernest Tai, "Talking About Death: Patterns of Lay and Profes- sional Change," Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science 447 (Jan- uary 1980), pp. 29-45. 44. August Hollingshead and Fredrick C. Redlich, Social Class and Mental Illness: A Community Study (New York: John Wiley & Sons, 1966, reprint of 1958 edition), p. 314.

Next: Secondary Income from Recommended Treatment: Should Fiduciary Principles Constrain Physician Behavior? »
The New Health Care for Profit: Doctors and Hospitals in a Competitive Environment Get This Book
×
 The New Health Care for Profit: Doctors and Hospitals in a Competitive Environment
Buy Paperback | $53.00
MyNAP members save 10% online.
Login or Register to save!
Download Free PDF

READ FREE ONLINE

  1. ×

    Welcome to OpenBook!

    You're looking at OpenBook, NAP.edu's online reading room since 1999. Based on feedback from you, our users, we've made some improvements that make it easier than ever to read thousands of publications on our website.

    Do you want to take a quick tour of the OpenBook's features?

    No Thanks Take a Tour »
  2. ×

    Show this book's table of contents, where you can jump to any chapter by name.

    « Back Next »
  3. ×

    ...or use these buttons to go back to the previous chapter or skip to the next one.

    « Back Next »
  4. ×

    Jump up to the previous page or down to the next one. Also, you can type in a page number and press Enter to go directly to that page in the book.

    « Back Next »
  5. ×

    To search the entire text of this book, type in your search term here and press Enter.

    « Back Next »
  6. ×

    Share a link to this book page on your preferred social network or via email.

    « Back Next »
  7. ×

    View our suggested citation for this chapter.

    « Back Next »
  8. ×

    Ready to take your reading offline? Click here to buy this book in print or download it as a free PDF, if available.

    « Back Next »
Stay Connected!